Section 2.5: The Decline of Natural Law

A Decorative Banner stating the title of this textbook: Fundamentals of Criminology by Adam J. McKee

The evolution of legal thought over the centuries witnessed a significant shift from the predominance of Natural Law to more empirical and skeptical approaches. This transition, marked by the contributions of key thinkers such as Thomas Hobbes and culminating with David Hume, represents a pivotal change in the philosophical underpinnings of law and morality.

Video Overview

Video Overviews of Section 2.5 are available on YouTube:

  • Video Content for this section is not yet available.

Reading Time: 11 minutes

Hobbes, with his emphasis on a strong sovereign authority to manage the innate conflictual nature of humans, began to steer away from the traditional Natural Law doctrine that saw moral and legal principles as inherent and discoverable through reason. His perspective laid the groundwork for a more pragmatic approach to understanding law and governance, focusing on the needs and conditions of human society rather than on universal moral precepts.

David Hume, a critical figure in this philosophical transition, further accelerated the decline of Natural Law. Hume, known for his profound skepticism and empirical methodology, challenged the very foundations of Natural Law. He argued against the existence of innate moral principles, positing that morality stems from feelings and social conventions rather than from any natural order. Hume’s approach represented a radical departure from the traditional viewpoints, reshaping the landscape of legal and moral philosophy and paving the way for modern perspectives that emphasize empirical observation and human experience in understanding law and ethics.

Hume’s Critique of Natural Law

David Hume’s critique of Natural Law was fundamentally rooted in his challenge to the doctrine of Right Reason. Hume systematically deconstructed the idea that moral truths could be deduced through reason alone, a cornerstone of Natural Law theory. In his philosophical inquiries, Hume argued that reason is inherently a slave to the passions and cannot be the source of moral judgments.

Hume posited that human reasoning is limited to understanding matters of fact and relations of ideas. However, it cannot ascertain moral principles, which he believed were not objective truths but rather subjective experiences. His skepticism extended to the notion that reason could inherently lead to moral or ethical truths, a key component of Natural Law. This stance represented a significant departure from traditional Natural Law theorists, who believed that moral and legal principles could be discerned through rational thought.

Hume’s Rejection of Natural Law

Hume’s rejection of Natural Law centers around his belief that morality and virtue stem not from reason but from human emotions and feelings. He argued that moral decisions and judgments are more akin to the appreciation of art rather than the outcome of logical reasoning. For Hume, moral and ethical feelings are a result of our psychological disposition and societal influences rather than any innate natural order.

Hume contested the notion that there exists a universal moral code discoverable through reason, a fundamental aspect of Natural Law theory. Instead, he suggested that what people consider virtuous or moral is heavily influenced by their feelings of approval or disapproval, shaped by cultural norms and personal experiences. This subjective basis for morality undermines the concept of a natural, objective moral order that can be universally applied, a key tenet of Natural Law.

The Shift from Philosophical to Scientific Inquiry

Hume’s approach to morality and ethics marked a significant shift from traditional philosophical inquiry to a more empirical and scientific method. He redefined the concept of science in the context of human behavior and ethics, focusing on empirical observation and the analysis of human nature.

Hume emphasized that our understanding of morality should be based on the study of human nature, employing observational and empirical methods. This perspective was revolutionary in moving away from the abstract, deductive reasoning of traditional Natural Law theorists to an approach grounded in the observation of human behavior and societal norms.

His methodological shift laid the groundwork for the development of social sciences, where the study of human behavior, society, and ethics is based on empirical evidence and observation rather than solely on deductive reasoning. Hume’s legacy in redefining the approach to understanding law and morality continues to influence contemporary legal and ethical studies, emphasizing the importance of empirical evidence in formulating legal and moral principles.

Impact of Hume’s Philosophy 

David Hume’s philosophy radically alters the traditional view of morality by proposing that it is a construct of human feelings, education, and societal conventions, rather than an innate aspect of natural law. In Hume’s perspective, moral perceptions are subjective, akin to our responses to beauty or disgust, and are primarily shaped by our emotional responses to actions and characters.

Hume argued that the pleasure or displeasure influences our moral judgments we feel when considering certain behaviors or characters. This emotive basis of morality means that our ethical perceptions are cultivated through life experiences, societal interactions, and education, rather than being derived from some inherent moral code. Education, in this context, is crucial as it shapes our emotional responses and guides us in aligning with the moral standards of our society.

This view has significant implications for legal and moral thought. It suggests that moral and ethical standards are fluid and can vary between different societies and cultures. It also implies that moral education and societal conditioning play a critical role in shaping an individual’s ethical framework, challenging the notion of universal moral principles that apply irrespective of context.

The Role of Society and Conventions in Shaping Justice

Hume’s belief in the artificial nature of justice as emerging from societal conventions and collective agreements marks a departure from the idea of an innate sense of justice. According to Hume, justice is not a natural virtue but a construct developed through human interaction and agreement, essential for the functioning of society.

He posited that justice arises from the practical necessities of human coexistence. In a world where resources are limited, and interests often conflict, societies develop systems of justice to mediate these conflicts and facilitate social harmony. Justice, therefore, is a set of conventions that are agreed upon for mutual benefit and the collective good.

This perspective has a profound impact on legal theory, suggesting that laws and legal systems are products of social contracts and agreements, rather than reflections of a natural moral order. It emphasizes the role of societal consensus in defining what is just and equitable. Hume’s view also underscores the importance of understanding the context and social dynamics in which laws are formed and applied.

In conclusion, Hume’s philosophy offers a nuanced understanding of morality and justice as products of human emotions, education, societal norms, and collective agreements. This perspective challenges traditional notions of natural law and universal justice, contributing to a more relativistic and context-dependent approach in legal and moral philosophy.

Comparison with Aristotle and Other Thinkers

David Hume’s and Aristotle’s perspectives on the evolution of the state and the role of the family exhibit both similarities and differences. Aristotle viewed the state as a natural extension of the family, evolving from the basic familial unit to villages and eventually to a polis or state. He saw the state as a culmination of natural social bonds, with the family playing a foundational role in the development of society.

Hume, while agreeing on the significance of the family as a basic social unit, diverged from Aristotle in his view of the state’s evolution. Unlike Aristotle, who saw the state as a natural and necessary entity for achieving the good life, Hume perceived the formation of states and societies as driven more by practical needs and expediency than natural social inclinations. For Hume, the state is not a natural evolution but a construct developed out of necessity to manage conflicts and provide security in a world where resources are scarce.

This difference highlights a fundamental divergence between Hume’s more pragmatic, utilitarian view of societal development and Aristotle’s more organic, naturalistic perspective. While both acknowledge the family’s role in forming societies, their views on the nature and purpose of the state reflect differing philosophical underpinnings.

The Evolution of State and Society in Hume’s Philosophy

In Hume’s philosophy, the evolution of states and societies from basic family units is characterized by a pragmatic approach. Hume saw the family as the initial stage in the development of more complex social structures, acknowledging its role in providing security, nurturing, and the basic organization of human relations.

However, Hume emphasized that as societies grow, the familial bonds and direct interpersonal relationships become insufficient to manage broader social interactions and conflicts. Thus, the formation of larger societal structures, including states, becomes necessary for practical reasons – to protect property, enforce contracts, and ensure collective security.

Hume’s analysis suggests that societal and state formations are responses to the challenges posed by increasing population sizes and complexity of human interactions. These structures are not seen as natural or inevitable but as artificial constructs developed to address specific human needs and circumstances. This perspective implies a more calculated and deliberate formation of social institutions, highlighting the role of human convention and agreement in the development of societal and state structures.

The Decline of Natural Law in Modern Jurisprudence

David Hume’s philosophy played a crucial role in the transition from Natural Law to legal positivism in modern jurisprudence. His skepticism towards the existence of innate moral principles and his emphasis on empirical observation and human experience laid the groundwork for the development of legal positivism. Legal positivism, as a school of thought, asserts that laws are rules created by human beings and are not necessarily tied to moral norms or natural rights.

Hume’s contention that moral judgments stem from emotions and societal conventions, rather than any inherent natural law, challenged the foundation of Natural Law theory, which posited that legal principles could be discerned through rational thought and were universal. Hume’s approach shifted the focus from seeking universal moral and legal principles to understanding law as a human construct, subject to the changing dynamics of society and culture.

This shift led to an emphasis on the codification of laws and the analysis of legal systems as they are, rather than as they ought to be based on some higher moral order. Legal positivism focuses on the written and enacted laws, advocating for a separation of law and morality. Hume’s influence is evident in this approach, as it aligns with his views on the empirical study of human behavior and the societal basis of legal and moral standards.

Contemporary Relevance and Critiques

The contemporary relevance of Hume’s critiques of Natural Law is significant in the ongoing discussions in legal and moral philosophy. His ideas continue to influence debates on the nature of law, the relationship between law and morality, and the origins of legal principles. In an era where legal systems are increasingly seen as dynamic and culturally contingent, Hume’s perspectives provide a framework for understanding law as a product of human convention and practical necessity.

However, Hume’s views also face critiques, particularly from those who argue for a moral basis in law. Critics of legal positivism, drawing from Natural Law theory, contend that disconnecting law from moral values can lead to legal systems that are unjust or inhumane. They argue for the importance of moral reasoning in legal decision-making and the recognition of universal human rights as a basis for legal norms.

Additionally, in the context of globalization and international law, the question of universal moral and legal standards has gained renewed importance. Here, Hume’s skepticism about universal moral principles is challenged by the need for common legal frameworks that transcend cultural and societal differences.

In conclusion, Hume’s critiques of Natural Law have had a lasting impact on legal thought, contributing to the development of legal positivism and shaping contemporary discussions in jurisprudence. While his ideas remain influential, they also invite ongoing debate and critique in the evolving landscape of legal and moral philosophy.

Summary and Conclusion

The philosophical journey from Natural Law to a more empirical approach in legal theory, significantly influenced by David Hume, marks a critical shift in the landscape of legal and moral thought. Hume’s skepticism towards Natural Law and his emphasis on human experience, emotions, and societal conventions played a pivotal role in this transition, reshaping how we understand the foundations and functions of law.

Hume’s critique of Natural Law, challenging its premise of innate moral principles discernible through reason, brought a profound change in jurisprudence. He posited that moral and legal norms are not universal truths but constructs shaped by human emotions and societal needs. This perspective questioned the Natural Law’s assertion of a moral order inherent in the universe, suggesting instead that legal systems are human creations, subject to the complexities and variations of human society.

This shift from a Natural Law framework to legal positivism, with its focus on positive laws as human-made rules, has had far-reaching implications for modern law, criminology, and political science. It underpins a view of law as a dynamic and context-dependent system, rather than a reflection of a universal moral order. This has influenced the development of diverse legal systems that reflect the cultural, social, and historical contexts in which they operate.

In criminology, Hume’s ideas have contributed to the understanding of criminal behavior as influenced by societal factors and human nature, rather than solely by moral failing or deviation from natural laws. In political science, his perspective has encouraged a more pragmatic approach to understanding state formation, governance, and legal systems.

The significance of this philosophical shift is evident in the ongoing debates in legal and moral philosophy, where the balance between empirical legal approaches and moral reasoning continues to be a central concern. The move towards more empirical approaches has fostered a more nuanced understanding of law as a social instrument that evolves with human society.

In conclusion, understanding the transition from Natural Law to empirical legal theory is crucial for comprehending the complexities of contemporary legal systems. Hume’s influence in this transition highlights the importance of considering human nature, societal contexts, and practical needs in the formulation and application of laws. His legacy remains integral to our ongoing efforts to reconcile the demands of justice, societal needs, and the ever-changing human condition in the realm of law and governance.

Modification History

File Created:  08/04/2018

Last Modified:  01/21/2024

[ Back | Content | Next]


This work is licensed under an Open Educational Resource-Quality Master Source (OER-QMS) License.

Open Education Resource--Quality Master Source License

Print for Personal Use

You are welcome to print a copy of pages from this Open Educational Resource (OER) book for your personal use. Please note that mass distribution, commercial use, or the creation of altered versions of the content for distribution are strictly prohibited. This permission is intended to support your individual learning needs while maintaining the integrity of the material.

Print This Text Section Print This Text Section

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.